Newsletter Subject

Dominance: Ukraine's Unprecedented Strike on A-50 - March 28

From

targetlinenews.com

Email Address

get@your.targetlinenews.com

Sent On

Thu, Mar 28, 2024 09:48 PM

Email Preheader Text

This historic triumph astounds the Russian army and the world. How? What tech was used? The Critical

This historic triumph astounds the Russian army and the world. How? What tech was used? [Target Line News] Breaking: Ukraine Downs Russian A-50 with AI, Shaking Global Military Landscape! Influences[edit] The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) was a major influence on Hegel. As H. S. Harris recounts, when Hegel entered the Tübingen seminary in 1788, "he was a typical product of the German Enlightenment – an enthusiastic reader of Rousseau and Lessing, acquainted with Kant (at least at second hand), but perhaps more deeply devoted to the classics than to any thing modern."[58] During this early period of his life "the Greeks – especially Plato – came first."[59] Although he later elevated Aristotle above Plato, Hegel never abandoned his love of ancient philosophy, the imprint of which is everywhere in his thought.[60] Aristotle (384–322 BC) and the ancient Greeks were also a major influence. Hegel's concern with various forms of cultural unity (Judaic, Greek, medieval, and modern) during this early period would remain with him throughout his career.[61] In this way, he was also a typical product of early German romanticism.[62] "Unity of life" was the phrase used by Hegel and his generation to express their concept of the highest good. It encompasses unity "with oneself, with others, and with nature. The main threat to such unity consists in division (Entzweiung) or alienation (Entfremdung)."[63] In this respect, Hegel was particularly taken with the phenomenon of love as a kind of "unity-in-difference," this both in the ancient articulation provided by Plato and in the Christian religion's doctrine of agape, which Hegel at this time viewed as "already 'grounded on universal Reason.'"[64][65] This interest, as well as his theological training, would continue to mark his thought, even as it developed in a more theoretical or metaphysical direction.[b] According to Glenn Alexander Magee, Hegel's thought (in particular, the tripartite structure of his system) also owes much to the hermetic tradition, in particular, the work of Jakob Böhme.[67] The conviction that philosophy must take the form of a system Hegel owed, most particularly, to his Tübingen roommates, Schelling and Hölderlin.[68] Hegel also read widely and was much influenced by Adam Smith and other theorists of the political economy.[69] It was Kant's Critical Philosophy that provided what Hegel took as the definitive modern articulation of the divisions that must be overcome.[70] This led to his engagement with the philosophical programs of Fichte and Schelling, as well as his attention to Spinoza and the Pantheism controversy.[71][c] The influence of Johann Gottfried von Herder, however, would lead Hegel to a qualified rejection of the universality claimed by the Kantian program in favor of a more culturally, linguistically, and historically informed account of reason.[72] Philosophical system[edit] See also: Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences Hegel's philosophical system is divided into three parts: the science of logic, the philosophy of nature, and the philosophy of spirit (the latter two of which together constitute the real philosophy). This structure is adopted from Proclus's Neoplatonic triad of "'remaining-procession-return' and from the Christian Trinity."[73][d] Although evident in draft writings dating back as early as 1805, the system was not completed in published form until the 1817 Encyclopedia (1st ed.).[75] Frederick C. Beiser argues that the position of the logic with respect to the real philosophy is best understood in terms of Hegel's appropriation of Aristotle's distinction between "the order of explanation" and "the order of being."[e] To Beiser, Hegel is neither a Platonist who believes in abstract logical entities, nor a nominalist according to whom the particular is first in the orders of explanation and being alike. Rather, Hegel is a holist. For Hegel, the universal is always first in the order of explanation even if what is naturally particular is first in the order of being. With respect to the system as a whole, that universal is supplied by the logic.[77] Michael J. Inwood plainly states, "The logical idea is non-temporal and therefore does not exist at any time apart from its manifestations." To ask "when" it divides into nature and spirit is analogous to asking "when" 12 divides into 5 and 7. The question does not have an answer because it is predicated upon a fundamental misunderstanding of its terms.[78] The task of the logic (at this high systemic level) is to articulate what Hegel calls "the identity of identity and non-identity" of nature and spirit. Put another way, it aims to overcome subject-object dualism.[79] This is to say that, among other things, Hegel's philosophical project endeavors to provide the metaphysical basis for an account of spirit that is continuous with, yet distinct from, the "merely" natural world – without thereby reducing either term to the other.[80] Furthermore, the final sections of Hegel's Encyclopedia suggest that to give priority to any one of its three parts is to have an interpretation that is "one-sided," incomplete or otherwise inaccurate.[81][80][82] As Hegel famously declares, "The true is the whole."[83] The Phenomenology of Spirit[edit] Main article: The Phenomenology of Spirit The Phenomenology of Spirit was published in 1807. This is the first time that, at the age of thirty-six, Hegel lays out "his own distinctive approach" and adopts an "outlook that is recognizably 'Hegelian' to the philosophical problems of post-Kantian philosophy.[84] Yet, the book was poorly understood even by Hegel's contemporaries and received mostly negative reviews.[85] To this day, the Phenomenology is infamous for, among other things, its conceptual and allusive density, idiosyncratic terminology, and confusing transitions.[86] Its most comprehensive commentary, scholar H. S. Harris's two-volume Hegel's Ladder (The Pilgrimage of Reason and The Odyssey of Spirit),[87] runs more than three times the length of the text itself.[88] The fourth chapter of the Phenomenology includes Hegel's first presentation of the lord-bondsman dialectic,[f] the section of the book that has been most influential in general culture.[91] What is at stake in the conflict Hegel presents is the practical (not theoretical) recognition or acknowledgement [Anerkennug, anerkennen] of the universality – e.g., personhood, humanity – of each of two opposed self-consciousnesses.[92][g] What the readers learn, but what the self-consciousnesses described do not yet realize, is that recognition can only be successful and actual as reciprocal or mutual.[95] This is the case for the simple reason that the recognition of someone you do not recognize as properly human cannot count as genuine recognition.[96] Hegel can also be seen here as criticizing the individualist worldview of people and society as a collection of atomized individuals, instead taking a holistic view of human self-consciousness as originating in recognition from others, and our view of ourselves being shaped by the views of others.[97] Title page of the original 1807 edition Hegel describes The Phenomenology as both the "introduction" to his philosophical system and also as the "first part" of that system as the "science of the experience of consciousness."[98] Yet it has long been controversial in both respects; indeed, Hegel's own attitude changed throughout his life.[h] Nevertheless, however complicated the details, the basic strategy by which it attempts to make good on its introductory claim is not difficult to state. Beginning with only the most basic "certainties of consciousness itself," "the most immediate of which is the certainty that I am conscious of this object, here and now," Hegel aims to show that these "certainties of natural consciousness" have as their consequence the standpoint of speculative logic.[99][100] This does not, however, make the Phenomenology a Bildungsroman. It is not the consciousness under observation that learns from its experience. Only "we," the phenomenological observers, are in a position to profit from Hegel's logical reconstruction of the science of experience.[101] The ensuing dialectic is long and hard. It is described by Hegel himself as a "path of despair," in which self-consciousness finds itself to be, over and again, in error.[102] It is the self-concept of consciousness itself that is tested in the domain of experience, and where that concept is not adequate, self-consciousness "suffers this violence at its own hands, and brings to ruin its own restricted satisfaction."[103][104] For, as Hegel points out, one cannot learn how to swim without getting into the water.[105] By progressively testing its concept of knowledge in this way, by "making experience his standard of knowledge, Hegel is embarking upon nothing less than a transcendental deduction of metaphysics."[106][i] In the course of its dialectic, the Phenomenology purports to demonstrate that – because consciousness always includes self-consciousness – there are no 'given' objects of direct awareness not already mediated by thought. Further analysis of the structure of self-consciousness reveals that both the social and conceptual stability of our experiential world depend upon networks of reciprocal recognition. Failures of recognition, then, demand reflection upon the past as a way "to understand what is required of us at the present." For Hegel, this ultimately involves rethinking an interpretation of "religion as the collective reflection of the modern community on what ultimately counts for it." He contends, finally, that this "historically, socially construed philosophical account of that whole process" elucidates our distinctly "modern" standpoint and its genesis.[108] Another way of putting this is to say that the Phenomenology takes up Kant's philosophical project of investigating the capacities and limits of reason. Under the influence of Herder, however, Hegel proceeds historically, instead of altogether a priori. Yet, although proceeding historically, Hegel resists the relativistic consequences of Herder's own thought. In the words of one scholar, "It is Hegel's insight that reason itself has a history, that what counts as reason is the result of a development. This is something that Kant never imagines and that Herder only glimpses."[81] In praise of Hegel's accomplishment, Walter Kaufmann writes that the guiding conviction of the Phenomenology is that a philosopher should not "confine him or herself to views that have been held but penetrate these to the human reality they reflect." In other words, it is not enough to consider propositions, or even the content of consciousness; "it is worthwhile to ask in every instance what kind of spirit would entertain such propositions, hold such views, and have such a consciousness. Every outlook in other words, is to be studied not merely as an academic possibility but as an existential reality."[109] What the reader of The Phenomenology of Spirit learns is that the search for an externally objective criterion of truth is a fool's errand. The constraints on knowledge are necessarily internal to spirit itself. Yet, although our theories and self-conceptions may always be reevaluated, renegotiated, and revised, this is not a merely imaginative exercise. Claims to knowledge must always prove their own adequacy in real historical experience.[110] Although Hegel seemed during his Berlin years to have abandoned The Phenomenology of Spirit, at the time of his unexpected death, he was in fact making plans to revise and republish it. As he was no longer in need of money or credentials, H. S. Harris argues that "the only rational conclusion that can be drawn from his decision to republish the book… is that he still regarded the 'science of experience' as a valid project in itself" and one for which later system has no equivalent.[111] There is, however, no scholarly consensus about the Phenomenology with respect to either of the systematic roles asserted by Hegel at the time of its publication.[j][k] Science of Logic[edit] Main article: Science of Logic Hegel's concept of logic differs greatly from that of the ordinary English sense of the term. This can be seen, for instance, in such metaphysical definitions of logic as "the science of things grasped in [the] thoughts that used to be taken to express the essentialities of the things."[113] As Michael Wolff explains, Hegel's logic is a continuation of Kant's distinctive logical program.[114] Its occasional engagement with the familiar Aristotelian conception of logic is only incidental to Hegel's project. Twentieth-century developments by such logicians as Frege and Russell likewise remain logics of formal validity and so are likewise irrelevant to Hegel's project, which aspires to provide a metaphysical logic of truth.[115] There are two versions of Hegel's Logic. The first, The Science of Logic (1812, 1813, 1816; bk.I revised 1831), is sometimes also called the "Greater Logic." The second is the first volume of Hegel's Encyclopedia and is sometimes known as the "Lesser Logic." The Encyclopedia Logic is an abbreviated or condensed presentation of the same dialectic. Hegel composed it for use with students in the lecture hall, not as a substitute for its proper, book-length exposition.[116][l] Hegel presents logic as a presuppositionless science that investigates the most fundamental thought-determinations [Denkbestimmungen], or categories, and so constitutes the basis of philosophy.[118][119] In putting something into question, one already presupposes logic; in this regard, it is the only field of inquiry that must constantly reflect upon its own mode of functioning.[120] The Science of Logic is Hegel's attempt to meet this foundational demand.[m] As he puts it, "logic coincides with metaphysics."[113][121] It is important to see, however, that Hegel's metaphysical program is not a return to the Leibnizian-Wolffian rationalism critiqued by Kant, which is a criticism Hegel accepts.[122] In particular, Hegel rejects any form of metaphysics as speculation about the transcendent. His procedure, an appropriation of Aristotle's concept of form, is fully immanent.[123] More generally, Hegel agrees wholeheartedly with Kant's rejection of all forms of dogmatism and also agrees that any future metaphysics must pass the test of criticism.[124] It is the assessment of scholar Stephen Houlgate that Hegel's method of immanent logical development and critique is historically unique.[125] Béatrice Longuenesse holds that this project may be understood, on analogy to Kant, as "inseparably a metaphysical and a transcendental deduction of the categories of metaphysics."[126][n] This approach insists, and claims to demonstrate, that the insights of logic cannot be judged by standards external to thought itself, that is, that "thought... is not the mirror of nature." Yet, she argues, this does not imply that these standards are arbitrary or subjective.[126] Hegel's translator and scholar of German idealism George di Giovanni likewise interprets the Logic as (drawing upon, yet also in opposition to, Kant) immanently transcendental; its categories, according to Hegel, are built into life itself, and define what it is to be "an object in general."[128] Books one and two of the Logic are the doctrines of "Being" and "Essence." Together they comprise the Objective Logic, which is largely occupied with overcoming the assumptions of traditional metaphysics. Book three is the final part of the Logic. It discusses the doctrine of "the Concept," which is concerned with reintegrating those categories of objectivity into a thoroughly idealistic account of reality.[o] Simplifying greatly, Being describes its concepts just as they appear, Essence attempts to explain them with reference to other forces, and the Concept explains and unites them both in terms of an internal teleology.[130] The categories of Being "pass over" from one to the next as denoting thought-determinations only extrinsically connected to one another. The categories of Essence reciprocally "shine" into one another. Finally, in the Concept, thought has shown itself to be fully self-referential, and so its categories organically "develop" from one to the next.[131][132] It is clear then, that in Hegel's technical sense of the term, the concept (Begriff, sometimes also rendered "notion," capitalized by some translators but not others[p]) is not a psychological concept. When deployed with the definitive article ("the") and sometimes modified by the term "logical," Hegel is referring to the intelligible structure of reality as articulated in the Subjective Logic. (When used in the plural, however, Hegel's sense is much closer to the ordinary dictionary sense of the term.)[134] Hegel's inquiry into thought is concerned to systematize thought's own internal self-differentiation, that is, how pure concepts (logical categories) differ from one another in their various relations of implication and interdependence. For instance, in the opening dialectic of the Logic, Hegel claims to display that the thought of "being, pure being – without further determination" is indistinguishable from the concept of nothing, and that, in this "passing back and forth" of being and nothing, "each immediately vanishes in its opposite."[135] This movement is neither one concept nor the other, but the category of becoming. There is not a difference here to which we can "refer," only a dialectic that we can observe and describe.[136] The final category of the Logic is "the idea." As with "the concept", the sense of this term for Hegel is not psychological. Rather, following Kant in The Critique of Pure Reason, Hegel's usage harks back to the Greek eidos, Plato's concept of form that is fully existent and universal:[137] "Hegel's Idee (like Plato's idea) is the product of an attempt to fuse ontology, epistemology, evaluation, etc., into a single set of concepts."[138] The Logic accommodates within itself the necessity of the realm of natural-spiritual contingency, that which cannot be determined in advance: "To go further, it must abandon thinking altogether and let itself go, opening itself to that which is other than thought in pure receptivity."[139] Simply put, logic realizes itself only in the domain of nature and spirit, in which it attains its "verification."[q] Hence the conclusion of the Science of Logic with "the idea freely discharging [entläßt] itself" into "objectivity and external life" – and, so too, the systematic transition to the Realphilosophie.[141][142] Philosophy of the real[edit] Hegel uses the Owl of Minerva as a metaphor for how philosophy can understand historical conditions only after they occur. See also: Realphilosophie In contrast to the first, logical part of Hegel's system, the second, real-philosophical part – the Philosophy of Nature and of Spirit – is an ongoing historical project. It is, as Hegel puts it, "its own time comprehended in thoughts."[143] Hegel expands upon this definition: A further word on the subject of issuing instructions on how the world ought to be: philosophy, at any rate, always comes too late to perform this function. As the thought of the world, it appears only at a time when actuality has gone through its formative process and attained its completed state [sich fertig gemacht]. This lesson of the concept is necessarily also apparent from history, namely that it is only when actuality [Wirklichkeit] has reached maturity that the ideal appears opposite the real and reconstructs this real world, which it has grasped in its substance, in the shape of an intellectual realm. When philosophy paints its gray in gray, a shape of life has grown old, and it cannot be rejuvenated, but only recognized, by the gray in gray of philosophy; the owl of Minerva begins its flight only with the onset of dusk.[144] This easily reads – and frequently has been read – as an expression of the impotence of philosophy, political or otherwise, and a rationalization of the status quo.[145] Allegra de Laurentiis, however, points out that the German expression "sich fertig machen" does not only imply completion, but also preparedness. This additional meaning is important because it better reflects Hegel's Aristotelian concept of actuality. He characterizes actuality as being-at-work-staying-itself that can never be once-and-for-all completed or finished.[146] Hegel describes the relationship between the logical and the real-philosophical parts of his system in this way: "If philosophy does not stand above its time in content, it does so in form, because, as the thought and knowledge of that which is the substantial spirit of its time, it makes that spirit its object."[147] This is to say that what makes the philosophy of the real scientific in Hegel's technical sense is the systematically coherent logical form it uncovers in its natural-historical material – and so also displays in its presentation.[148] The Philosophy of Nature[edit] See also: Naturphilosophie The philosophy of nature organizes the contingent material of the natural sciences systematically. As part of the philosophy of the real, in no way does it presume to "tell nature what it must be like."[149][150] Historically, various interpreters have questioned Hegel's understanding of the natural sciences of his time. However, this claim has been largely refuted by recent scholarship.[151] One of the very few ways in which the philosophy of nature might correct claims made by the natural sciences themselves is to combat reductive explanations; that is to discredit accounts employing categories not adequate to the complexity of the phenomena they purport to explain, as for instance, attempting to explain life in strictly chemical terms.[152] Although Hegel and other Naturphilosophen aim to revive a teleological understanding of nature, they argue that their strictly internal or immanent concept of teleology is "limited to the ends observable within nature itself." Hence, they claim, it does not violate the Kantian critique.[153] Even more strongly, Hegel and Schelling claim that Kant's restriction of teleology to regulative status effectively undermines his own critical project of explaining the possibility of knowledge. Their argument is that "only under the assumption that there is an organism is it possible to explain the actual interaction between the subjective and the objective, the ideal and the real." Hence the organism must be acknowledged to have constitutive status.[154] Introducing Hegel's philosophy of nature for a 21st-century audience, Dieter Wandschneider [de] observes that "contemporary philosophy of science" has lost sight of "the ontological issue at stake, namely, the question of an intrinsically lawful nature": "Consider, for example, the problem of what constitutes a law of nature. This problem is central to our understanding of nature. Yet philosophy of science has not provided a definitive response to it up to now. Nor can we expect to have such an answer from that quarter in future."[155] It is back to Hegel that Wandschneider would direct philosophers of science for guidance in the philosophy of nature.[156] Recent scholars have also argued that Hegel's approach to the philosophy of nature provides valuable resources for theorizing and confronting recent environmental challenges entirely unforeseen by Hegel. These philosophers point to such aspects of his philosophy as its distinctive metaphysical grounding and the continuity of its conception of the nature-spirit relationship.[157][158] The Philosophy of Spirit[edit] Priestess of Delphi (1891) by John Collier. The Delphic imperative to "know thyself" governs Hegel's entire philosophy of spirit. The German Geist has a wide range of meanings.[159] In its most general Hegelian sense, however, "Geist denotes the human mind and its products, in contrast to nature and also the logical idea."[160] (Some older translations render it as "mind," rather than "spirit."[r]) As is especially evident in the Anthropology, Hegel's concept of spirit is an appropriation and transformation of the self-referential Aristotelian concept of energeia.[162] Spirit is not something above or otherwise external to nature. It is "the highest organization and development" of nature's powers.[163] According to Hegel, "the essence of spirit is freedom."[164] The Encyclopedia Philosophy of Spirit charts the progressively determinate stages of this freedom until spirit fulfills the Delphic imperative with which Hegel begins: "Know thyself."[165] As becomes clear, Hegel's concept of freedom is not (or not merely) the capacity for arbitrary choice, but has as its "core notion" that "something, especially a person, is free if and only if, it is independent and self-determining, not determined by or dependent upon something other than itself."[166] It is, in other words, (at least predominantly, dialectically) an account of what Isaiah Berlin would later term positive liberty.[167] Subjective spirit[edit] Standing at the transition from nature to spirit, the role of the Philosophy of Subjective Spirit is to analyze "the elements necessary for or presupposed by such relations [of objective spirit], namely, the structures characteristic of and necessary to the individual rational agent." It does this by elaborating "the fundamental nature of the biological/spiritual human individual along with the cognitive and the practical prerequisites of human social interaction."[168] This section, particularly its first part, contains various comments that were commonplace in Hegel's day and we now recognize as openly racist, such as unfounded claims about the "naturally" lower intellectual and emotional development of Black people. In his perspective, these racial differences are related to climate: according to Hegel, it is not racial characteristics, but the climactic conditions in which a people lives that variously limit or enable its capacity for free self-determination. He believes that race is not destiny: any group could, in principle, improve and transform its condition by migrating to friendlier climes.[169][s] Hegel divides his philosophy of the subjective spirit into three parts: anthropology, phenomenology, and psychology. Anthropology "deals with 'soul', which is spirit still mired in nature: all that within us which precedes our self-conscious mind or intellect." In the section "Phenomenology", Hegel examines the relation between consciousness and its object and the emergence of intersubjective rationality. Psychology "deals with a great deal that would be categorized as epistemology (or 'theory of knowledge') today. Hegel discusses, among other things, the nature of attention, memory, imagination and judgement."[170] Throughout this section, but especially in the Anthropology, Hegel appropriates and develops Aristotle's hylomorphic approach to what is today theorized as the mind–body problem: "The solution to the mind–body problem [according to this theory] hinges upon recognizing that mind does not act upon the body as cause of effects but rather acts upon itself as an embodied living subjectivity. As such, mind develops itself, progressively attaining more and more of a self-determined character."[171][172] Its final section, Free Spirit, develops the concept of "free will," which is foundational for Hegel's philosophy of right.[173][174] Objective spirit[edit] Main article: Elements of the Philosophy of Right See also: Lectures on the Philosophy of History King Frederick William III of Prussia (1797—1840) stifled the political reforms for which Hegel had hoped and advocated.[175] In the broadest terms, Hegel's philosophy of objective spirit "is his social philosophy, his philosophy of how the human spirit objectifies itself in its social and historical activities and productions."[176] Or, put differently, it is an account of the institutionalization of freedom.[177] Besier declares this a rare instance of unanimity in Hegel scholarship: "all scholars agree there is no more important concept in Hegel's political theory than freedom." This is because it is the foundation of right, the essence of spirit, and the telos of history.[178] This part of Hegel's philosophy is presented first in his 1817 Encyclopedia (revised 1827 and 1830) and then at greater length in the 1821 Elements of the Philosophy of Right, or Natural Law and Political Science in Outline (like the Encyclopedia, intended as a textbook), upon which he also frequently lectured. Its final part, the philosophy of world history, was additionally elaborated in Hegel's lectures on the subject.[179][180] Hegel's Elements of the Philosophy of Right has been controversial from the date of its original publication.[181][182] It is not, however, a straightforward defense of the autocratic Prussian state, as some have alleged, but is rather a defense of "Prussia as it was to have become under [proposed] reform administrations."[183] The German Recht in Hegel's title does not have a direct English equivalent (though it does correspond to the Latin ius and the French droit). As a first approximation, Michael Inwood distinguishes three senses: a right, claim or title justice (as in, e.g., 'to administer justice'...but not justice as a virtue...) 'the law' as a principle, or 'the laws' collectively.[184] Beiser observes that Hegel's theory is "his attempt to rehabilitate the natural law tradition while taking into account the criticisms of the historical school." He adds that "without a sound interpretation of Hegel's theory of natural law, we have very little understanding of the very foundation of his social and political thought."[185][t] Consistent with Beiser's position, Adriaan T. Peperzak documents Hegel's arguments against social contract theory and stresses the metaphysical foundations of Hegel's philosophy of right.[189][u] Observing that "analyzing the structure of Hegel's argument in the Philosophy of Right shows that achieving political autonomy is fundamental to Hegel's analysis of the state and government," Kenneth R. Westphal provides this brief outline: "'Abstract Right,' treats principles governing property, its transfer, and wrongs against property." "'Morality,' treats the rights of moral subjects, responsibility for one's actions, and a priori theories of right." "'Ethical Life' (Sittlichkeit), analyzes the principles and institutions governing central aspects of rational social life, including the family, civil society, and the state as a whole, including the government."[191] Hegel describes the state of his time, a constitutional monarchy, as rationally embodying three cooperative and mutually inclusive elements. These elements are "democracy (rule of the many, who are involved in legislation), aristocracy (rule of the few, who apply, concretize, and execute the laws), and monarchy (rule of the one, who heads and encompasses all power)."[192][193] It is what Aristotle called a "mixed" form of government, which is designed to include what is best of each of the three classical forms.[194] The division of powers "prevents an single power from dominating others."[195] Hegel is particularly concerned to bind the monarch to the constitution, limiting his authority so that he can do little more than to declare of what his ministers have already decided that it is to be so.[196] The relation of Hegel's philosophy of right to modern liberalism is complex. He sees liberalism as a valuable and characteristic expression of the modern world. However, it carries the danger within itself to undermine its own values. This self-destructive tendency may be avoided by measuring "the subjective goals of individuals by a larger objective and collective good." Moral values, then, have only a "limited place in the total scheme of things."[197] Yet, although it is not without reason that Hegel is widely regarded as a major proponent of what Isaiah Berlin would later term positive liberty, he was just as "unwavering and unequivocal" in his defense of negative liberty.[198] If Hegel's ideal sovereign is much weaker than was typical in monarchies his time, so too is his democratic element much weaker than is typical in democracies of our time. Although he insists upon the importance of public participation, Hegel severely limits suffrage and follows the English bicameral model, in which only members of the lower house, that of commoners and bourgeoisie, are elected officials. Nobles in the upper house, like the monarch, inherit their positions.[199] The final part of the Philosophy of Objective Spirit is entitled "World History." In this section, Hegel argues that "this immanent principle [the Stoic logos] produces with logical inevitability an expansion of the species' capacities for self determination ('freedom') and a deepening of its self understanding ('self-knowing')."[200] In Hegel's own words: "World history is progress in the consciousness of freedom – a progress that we must comprehend conceptually."[201] (See also: Legacy, below, for further discussion of the complex legacy of Hegel's social and political philosophy.) Absolute spirit[edit] See also: Absolute (philosophy) Hegel with his Berlin students (1828 sketch by F. T. Kugler) Hegel's use of the term "absolute" is easily misunderstood. Inwood, however, clarifies: derived from the Latin absolutus, it means "not dependent on, conditional on, relative to or restricted by anything else; self-contained, perfect, complete."[202] For Hegel, this means that absolute knowing can only denote "an 'absolute relation' in which the ground of experience and the experiencing agent are one and the same: the object known is explicitly the subject who knows."[203] That is, the only "thing" (which is really an activity) that is truly absolute is that which is entirely self-conditioned, and according to Hegel, this only occurs when spirit takes itself up as its own object. The final section of his Philosophy of Spirit presents the three modes of such absolute knowing: art, religion, and philosophy.[v] It is with reference to different modalities of consciousness – intuition, representation, and comprehending thinking – that Hegel distinguishes the three modes of absolute knowing.[w] Frederick Beiser summarizes: "art, religion and philosophy all have the same object, the absolute or truth itself; but they consist in different forms of knowledge of it. Art presents the absolute in the form of immediate intuition (Anschauung); religion presents it in the form of representation (Vorstellung); and philosophy presents it in the form of concepts (Begriffe)."[205] Rüdiger Bubner additionally clarifies that the increase in conceptual transparency according to which these spheres are systematically ordered is not hierarchical in any evaluative sense.[206] Although Hegel's discussion of absolute spirit in the Encyclopedia is quite brief, he develops his account at length in lectures on the philosophy of fine art, the philosophy of religion, and the history of philosophy.[180] [New weapon]( This historic triumph astounds the Russian army and the world. How? What tech was used? In the vast expanse of the cosmos, where galaxies dance in celestial harmony and stars twinkle like scattered gems, there exists a realm beyond imagination. This is the realm of the Chronomancers, beings who wield the fabric of time itself as their tool. Within the Chronomancers' citadel, towering spires of crystalline essence pierce the sky, shimmering with the energy of aeons past and future. Here, amidst the whispers of temporal winds, the grand library of eternity stands, its shelves filled with tomes bound in the essence of forgotten epochs. At the heart of the citadel lies the Temporal Nexus, a nexus of swirling energies that connects all moments, past, present, and future. It is here that the Chronomancers gather, their minds attuned to the rhythms of the cosmos, their wills bending the very flow of time to their command. But even among the masters of time, there are those who seek to unravel the delicate tapestry of existence. The Temporal Wars, waged across epochs and realities, threaten to tear asunder the very fabric of reality itself. And in the shadows, a dark presence stirs, its intentions veiled in mystery and malice. Yet amidst the chaos, there is hope. For within the ranks of the Chronomancers, a chosen few emerge, their destinies intertwined with the fate of the cosmos. Bound by threads older than creation itself, they embark on a journey through the annals of time, seeking to restore balance to a universe on the brink of oblivion. Across the sands of time, they will venture, facing trials and tribulations beyond mortal comprehension. For the fate of all existence hangs in the balance, and only they possess the power to tip the scales in favor of light or darkness. And so, as the wheels of destiny turn and the stars continue their eternal dance, the saga of the Chronomancers unfolds, a tale of courage, sacrifice, and the enduring power of hope in the face of adversity. In the heart of a forgotten forest, where the trees whisper secrets of old and the sunlight filters through the leaves like liquid gold, there lies a hidden sanctuary untouched by time. Here, amidst the ancient groves and moss-covered stones, a small community thrives in harmony with nature. The people of this enclave are known as the Sylvanfolk, descendants of the guardians of the woodlands who have lived in symbiosis with the land for generations untold. Their homes are woven from the branches of the trees, their clothes dyed with the vibrant hues of wildflowers, and their spirits attuned to the rhythm of the earth. But beyond the borders of their sanctuary, darkness looms. A shadowy presence known only as the Blight spreads its tendrils, corrupting the land and driving creatures mad with its malevolent influence. The Sylvanfolk, ever vigilant, stand as the last bastion against this encroaching darkness, their bond with nature their greatest weapon. Amidst this turmoil, a young Sylvan named Eirian emerges as an unlikely hero. Born under the light of a rare celestial event, her destiny is intertwined with the fate of her people and the very balance of the natural world. With courage in her heart and the wisdom of her ancestors guiding her, she embarks on a journey to confront the Blight and restore harmony to the land. Joined by a band of loyal companions—a wise elder, a skilled hunter, and a mischievous sprite—Eirian traverses the wilds, facing challenges both mundane and mystical. Along the way, she discovers hidden truths about her heritage, uncovers ancient artifacts of power, and forges alliances with unlikely allies. But as the Blight grows stronger and its influence spreads, Eirian realizes that defeating it will require more than just bravery and strength. She must delve deep into the mysteries of the forest, unlock the secrets of the Sylvanfolk's past, and ultimately embrace her role as a guardian of the natural world. With the fate of the forest hanging in the balance, Eirian and her companions embark on a final quest—to confront the source of the Blight itself and vanquish it once and for all. In a climactic battle between light and darkness, they must summon all their courage, wisdom, and strength to emerge victorious and restore peace to the land. And so, as the sun sets on the ancient forest and the stars twinkle overhead, a new chapter begins—a testament to the enduring power of hope, friendship, and the untamed spirit of the wild.In the heart of a bustling metropolis, where skyscrapers reach for the heavens and neon lights paint the streets in vibrant hues, there exists a hidden world unknown to most. Beneath the surface of the city lies the Labyrinth, a sprawling network of tunnels and chambers that stretch for miles in every direction. Forgotten by time and shrouded in mystery, the Labyrinth is home to a diverse array of inhabitants—outcasts, adventurers, and those who seek refuge from the chaos above. Here, amidst the flickering torches and echoing footsteps, a society thrives in the shadows, its rules governed by the laws of survival and the code of the underground. At the heart of the Labyrinth lies the Nexus, a nexus of energy that pulses with a power as ancient as the city itself. It is here that a small band of rebels known as the Luminae gather, their mission to challenge the corrupt forces that control the surface world and bring light to the darkness below. Led by a charismatic leader named Asher, the Luminae are a motley crew of misfits and renegades, each with their own skills and secrets. Together, they navigate the treacherous passages of the Labyrinth, facing dangers both natural and supernatural as they seek to uncover the truth behind the city's secrets. But they are not alone in their quest. Along the way, they encounter allies and adversaries alike—a mysterious sorcerer who wields the power of shadows, a cunning thief with a heart of gold, and a reclusive scholar who holds the key to unlocking the secrets of the Nexus. As they journey deeper into the heart of the Labyrinth, the true nature of their mission becomes clear. The city above is on the brink of destruction, its foundations shaken by greed and corruption. Only by harnessing the power of the Nexus and uniting the disparate factions of the underground can the Luminae hope to save their home and bring about a new dawn for all who dwell within its shadowed embrace. In a final showdown against the forces of darkness, Asher and his companions must confront their own fears and doubts, drawing upon the strength of their bonds and the courage of their convictions. For the fate of the city—and perhaps the world itself—hangs in the balance, and only they possess the power to tip the scales in favor of hope or despair. And so, as the echoes of battle fade and the first rays of dawn pierce the darkness, a new era dawns in the heart of the Labyrinth—a testament to the resilience of the human spirit and the enduring power of light in even the darkest of times. In the realm of Gaia, where magic flows like rivers and dragons soar across the skies, there exists a kingdom known as Eldoria—a land of beauty and wonder, yet plagued by darkness and conflict. At the heart of Eldoria lies the city of Arcadia, a beacon of hope amidst the chaos that threatens to consume the realm. Within the walls of Arcadia, a young mage named Lysander dreams of a world where peace reigns and all beings live in harmony. Gifted with a rare talent for elemental magic, Lysander is destined for greatness, yet burdened by the weight of his own destiny. But as shadows gather on the horizon and whispers of ancient prophecies echo through the streets, Lysander's peaceful existence is shattered. A dark force known as the Shadowsworn has risen from the depths of the earth, its malevolent influence spreading like a cancer across the land. With the kingdom on the brink of collapse and the fate of all Gaia hanging in the balance, Lysander embarks on a perilous journey to confront the darkness and restore balance to the realm. Joined by a band of loyal companions—a fierce warrior, a cunning rogue, and a wise sage—Lysander ventures into the heart of the Shadowsworn's domain, facing trials and tribulations beyond imagination. But as they delve deeper into the darkness, Lysander discovers that the true nature of the Shadowsworn is more complex than he ever imagined. Born from the remnants of a long-forgotten civilization, the Shadowsworn seek not destruction, but redemption—a chance to reclaim their place in the world and right the wrongs of the past. In a final showdown beneath the shadow of the Bloodmoon, Lysander and his companions confront the leader of the Shadowsworn—a fallen hero consumed by grief and rage. With the power of friendship and the strength of their convictions, they stand against the darkness, their hearts aflame with the light of hope. And as the sun rises on a new day in Eldoria, the kingdom rejoices in the triumph of good over evil. But amidst the celebrations, Lysander knows that the journey is far from over. For in a world where darkness lurks in every shadow, the quest for peace is never truly complete. [Discover the details now and unveil the small company behind this breakthrough ]( In the annals of history, few events have shaken the foundations of nations as profoundly as the rise and fall of the Crimson Republic. Born from the flames of revolution and fueled by the aspirations of the oppressed, the Republic emerged as a beacon of hope in a world consumed by tyranny and inequality. But as the winds of change swept across the land, the dream of freedom gave way to the harsh realities of power and ambition, leading to a tragic downfall that would echo through the ages. Chapter 1: The Spark of Rebellion In the late 18th century, the Kingdom of Veridian stood as a bastion of aristocratic privilege, ruled by a monarchy indifferent to the suffering of its people. Faced with rampant poverty, social injustice, and political repression, discontent simmered beneath the surface, waiting for a catalyst to ignite the flames of revolution. That catalyst came in the form of a charismatic young idealist named Marcus Darrow, whose fiery speeches and radical ideas inspired a generation to rise up against their oppressors. Chapter 2: The Birth of the Republic In the spring of 1792, the streets of Veridian erupted in protest as thousands took to the barricades, demanding an end to the monarchy and the establishment of a new order based on equality and justice. Led by Darrow and his fellow revolutionaries, the rebels stormed the royal palace, overthrowing the old regime and declaring the birth of the Crimson Republic. With Darrow at its helm, the Republic promised a new era of liberty and fraternity for all its citizens, regardless of their station in life. Chapter 3: Triumph and Tribulation As the fledgling Republic took its first steps towards nationhood, it faced a myriad of challenges, both internal and external. Amidst the euphoria of liberation, old divisions resurfaced, threatening to tear the fabric of society apart. Meanwhile, neighboring monarchies viewed the Republic with suspicion and hostility, fearing the spread of revolution to their own lands. Undeterred, Darrow and his allies embarked on a campaign of reform and modernization, seeking to build a society that embodied the ideals of the Enlightenment. Chapter 4: Shadows of Betrayal But as the years passed and the Republic consolidated its power, cracks began to appear in the facade of unity. Ambitious politicians and military leaders vied for influence, while radicals accused Darrow of abandoning the principles that had inspired the revolution in the pursuit of personal glory. Amidst this atmosphere of intrigue and suspicion, whispers of conspiracy echoed through the halls of power, threatening to undermine the very foundations of the Republic. Chapter 5: The Fall from Grace In the summer of 1806, the Republic stood on the brink of civil war as rival factions clashed in the streets and the halls of government. Sensing an opportunity to seize power for themselves, opportunists and demagogues rallied to their banners, while Darrow struggled to hold the crumbling edifice of the Republic together. But in the end, it was not external enemies or internal strife that brought about the downfall of the Crimson Republic, but the hubris and ambition of its own leaders. In a fateful coup d'état, Darrow was betrayed by those he had once called allies, and the dream of freedom died with him. Chapter 6: Legacy of the Republic Though the Crimson Republic may have fallen, its legacy endures, a reminder of the power of ideas to shape the course of history. In the years that followed, the memory of Darrow and his comrades inspired countless revolutions and uprisings across the world, as oppressed peoples rose up against their oppressors in the name of liberty and equality. And though the Republic itself may have been consigned to the dustbin of history, its spirit lives on in the hearts of all who dare to dream of a better world. Conclusion: As we look back on the rise and fall of the Crimson Republic, let us remember not only the tragedy of its demise, but also the hope and idealism that drove its creation. For though revolutions may come and go, the struggle for freedom and justice is eternal, a flame that burns bright in the darkest of times.In the annals of history, few events have reverberated through the corridors of power like the Siege of Bastille. Occurring on July 14, 1789, this pivotal moment marked the beginning of the French Revolution, a tumultuous period that would reshape the course of European history. Through the eyes of fictional characters entwined with real historical figures, this narrative seeks to illuminate the drama, intrigue, and chaos of that fateful day. Chapter 1: Prelude to Revolution As the 18th century drew to a close, France stood on the brink of collapse. Years of economic mismanagement, social inequality, and political corruption had plunged the nation into turmoil, leaving its people disillusioned and desperate for change. Amidst this atmosphere of discontent, whispers of revolution spread like wildfire, fueled by the writings of Enlightenment philosophers and the example of recent uprisings in America. Chapter 2: The People's Fury On the morning of July 14th, 1789, the streets of Paris seethed with tension as rumors swirled of an impending crackdown by the royal authorities. Sensing an opportunity to strike a blow against tyranny, a diverse coalition of revolutionaries, commoners, and disgruntled soldiers gathered outside the formidable walls of the Bastille—a symbol of royal authority and oppression. Among them, fictional characters such as Jacques, a disillusioned veteran of the Seven Years' War, and Marie, a spirited seamstress with a burning desire for freedom, stand shoulder to shoulder with historical figures like Camille Desmoulins and Georges Danton. Chapter 3: The Storming of Bastille As the sun reached its zenith, the crowd surged forward, their cries for liberty echoing off the ancient stone walls of te fortress. Armed with makeshift weapons and fueled by righteous indignation, they launched a daring assault on the Bastille, defying the odds and overwhelming the defenders.midst the chaos of battle, Jacques and Marie find themselves swept up in the tide of history, their fates intertwined with the destiny of a nation on the brink of revolution. Chapter 4: Triumph and Tragedy By nightfall, the Bastille lay in ruins, its once-imposing towers reduced to rubble by the fury of the mob. But victory came at a steep price, as countless lives were lost in the struggle for freedom. ForJacques and Marie, the euphoria of victory is tempered by the harsh realities of war, as they grapple with the consequences of their actions and the uncertainty of the future. Chapter 5: The Aftermath In the aftermath of the siege, France finds itself at a crossroads, torn between the promise of a new dawn and the specter of civil war. As the revolutionaries seize control of Paris and the monarchy teeters on the brink of collapse, Jacques and Marie must navigate a treacherous landscape of shfting allegiances and competing ambitions. For in the crucible of revolution, the line between heroism and villainy is often blurred, and the price of freedom is paid in blood. Chapter 6: Legacy of Bastille Though the Siege of Bastille may have been but a single battle in the grand tapestry of history, its impact reverberates through the ages, a symbol of the power of the people to rise up against oppression and injustice. As we look back on that fateful day, let us remember the courage and sacrifice of those who dared to defy tyranny, and honor their memory by continuing the struggle for liberty and equality for all. Conclusion: As the echoes of revolution fade into the mists of time, the Siege of Bastille stands as a testament to the indomitable spirit of humanity in the face of adversity. Through the trials and tribulations of fictional characters like Jacques and Marie, we glimpse the hopes, fears, and aspirations of a nation in turmoil, and bear witness to the birth of a new era in the annals of history. [Privacy Policy]( [Privacy Policy]( [Terms&Conditions]( [Terms&Conditions]( [Unsubscribe]( [Unsubscribe]( Occasionally, our affiliate partners offer exclusive opportunities for Target Line News readers. We highly recommend carefully considering the message above. This email was created and sent to you by FIT, LLC, owner and operator of Target Line News (TLN). a good idea to us]( to make sure you get every email. If you encounter any issues, feel free to reach out to our [support team](mailto:support@targetlinenews.com) for assistance. 221 W 9th St # WіІmіngtоn, DЕ 19801 Copyright © 2024 Target Line News. All Rights Reserved.   Occasionally, our affiliate partners offer exclusive opportunities for Target Line News readers. We highly recommend carefully considering the message above. This email was created and sent to you by FIT, LLC, owner and operator of Target Line News (TLN). a good idea to us]( to make sure you get every email. If you encounter any issues, feel free to reach out to our [support team](mailto:support@targetlinenews.com) for assistance. 221 W 9th St # WіІmіngtоn, DЕ 19801 Copyright © 2024 Target Line News. All Rights Reserved.

EDM Keywords (889)

zenith years wrongs writings woven would worthwhile world work words word woodlands without within wisdom winds wildflowers wild wields wield whole whispers wheels well weight ways way war walls virtue violence violate villainy views view victory vanquish values valuable used use us unwavering unveil unravel unlocking universe universal unity uniting unites unequivocal understood understanding understand undermine underground uncovers uncover uncertainty unanimity tyranny typical two turmoil tunnels truth true triumph tribulations tribulation trials trees translators translator transition transformation transform transfer transcendent tragedy title tip times time tide throughout threatens thoughts thought though things thing therefore theory theorizing theorists theories theoretical text tested testament test terms term tension tempered telos teleology tech tear task tale taking taken system symbol symbiosis sylvanfolk swept suspicion survival surface supplied supernatural summer suffering successful substitute substance subjective subject studied students struggle structure strike stretch stresses strength streets storming station state standpoint standards standard stand stake spring spread spirit spinoza spheres speculation specter spark source soul something someone solution society social skills skies siege shrouded shown show shoulder shattered shaped shape shaken shadowsworn shadows shadow sent sense seen seek section secrets second search science scholar schelling scales say save sands saga sacrifice ruins ruin rubble rousseau role risen rise rights right rhythms rhythm revolution revive revised revise reverberated return result restriction restricted respect resilience required require republish republic renegades remnants reminder religion relative relationship relations relation related rejuvenated rejection reintegrating rehabilitate regard reform reflect referring reference refer redemption reconstructs recognized recognize recognition reclaim reciprocal rebellion reason realm really reality real reader read reach rationalization rather ranks rage race question quest quarter putting puts pursuit purport pure pulses published prussia provided provide protest promise project progress profoundly profit products product proclus procedure problem principles principle price presupposed presume present precedes praise practical power possible possibility possess position plunged platonist plato place pilgrimage philosophy philosopher phenomenon phenomenology phenomena perspective person perhaps perform people penetrate peace path past pass particularly particular part paris paid owl overwhelming overcoming outlook otherwise others originating organism orders order oppressors oppression oppressed opposition opportunity opportunists operator onset oneself one old odyssey odds occurs observe observation objectivity objective object nothing nightfall nexus next never neither need necessity necessary navigate nature natural nations nation name mystery mysteries myriad must mundane movement morning money monarchy monarchies monarch modern mode mob mists mission misfits mirror ministers minerva mind miles migrating method metaphysics metaphysical metaphor message merely memory members meet measuring means may masters mark marie many manifestations makes luminae love lost longer long logicians logical logic lived little line limits limited light life lies liberty let lesson length led lectures least learns leaders leader laws law launched late land ladder labyrinth known knowledge kingdom kind key kant justice judged journey jacques involved investigating investigates introduction intrigue intertwined interpretation internal interest interdependence intellect instance inspired insights insight inseparably inquiry injustice influential influence infamous inequality individuals indistinguishable independent increase include incidental imprint impotence important importance imply implication immediate illuminate ignite identity ideas ideals idealism ideal idea humanity hubris however horizon hoped hope honor homes home holist holds hold history hierarchical heroism herder hence helm held hegel heavens hearts heart heads harris harnessing harmony hard hangs hands halls guidance guardians guardian ground grief greed gray grasped grapple grace government good gone gold go glimpse generation gaia future fury fundamental function fueled friendship frequently frege freedom free fraternity foundations foundational foundation forth forms form forces fool follows followed flow flight flames flame first field fichte fears favor fate far fallen fall faced face facade fabric eyes expression express explicitly explanation explaining explain experience expect expansion exists existence exist execute example evil everywhere events even euphoria eternal establishment essentialities essence especially errand equality epistemology enough engagement energy end encyclopedia encounter encompasses enclave enable emergence emerge embodied embarks embark email elements eldoria elaborating either effects echoes earth early dustbin drove dream drawn downfall domain dogmatism doctrines doctrine divisions division divides divided distinction display discussion discusses difficult difference dialectic develops development developed determined determination details destruction destiny destined desperate despair designed describes described depths deployed dependent denote demonstrate democracies demise definition define defense defeating deepening declaring declare decision day date darrow darkness darkest dared dare crucible critique criticizing criticisms cries creation created course courage counts cosmos corruption corridors correspond convictions conviction controversial control contrast continuous continuity continuing continuation content contemporaries consume constraints constitutes consistent consist consigned consequences consequence consciousness conscious connects confront conflict confine conditional condition conclusion concerned concern conceptual concepts conception concept comprise complexity complex completed commonplace commoners command collection collapse cognitive code clear classics claims claim city chronomancers chosen chaos chance chambers challenges challenge certainty certainties central cause category categorized categories catalyst case carries capacity capacities cannot campaign built build brought brink brings bring breakthrough bravery branches bourgeoisie borders book bonds bond body blow blight birth bind bildungsroman beyond betrayed betrayal best beneath believes beiser beginning becoming become beauty beacon bastion bastille basis banners band balance back avoided authority attention attempts attempt attains attained atmosphere assumptions assumption assessment aspires aspirations aspects asking ask articulated articulate aristotle arguments argument argues argue arcadia arbitrary appropriation approach appears appear answer annals ancient analyzing analyze analysis analogy analogous among amidst ambition altogether also alone alleged aims ages age agape aftermath adversity advance adopts adopted adequate adequacy adds actuality actual activity actions acknowledged account according absolute abbreviated abandoning abandoned 88 50 196 1830 1807 1806 1805 1792 1788 166

Marketing emails from targetlinenews.com

View More
Sent On

13/05/2024

Sent On

13/05/2024

Sent On

12/05/2024

Sent On

12/05/2024

Sent On

12/05/2024

Sent On

12/05/2024

Email Content Statistics

Subscribe Now

Subject Line Length

Data shows that subject lines with 6 to 10 words generated 21 percent higher open rate.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Number of Words

The more words in the content, the more time the user will need to spend reading. Get straight to the point with catchy short phrases and interesting photos and graphics.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Number of Images

More images or large images might cause the email to load slower. Aim for a balance of words and images.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Time to Read

Longer reading time requires more attention and patience from users. Aim for short phrases and catchy keywords.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Predicted open rate

Subscribe Now

Spam Score

Spam score is determined by a large number of checks performed on the content of the email. For the best delivery results, it is advised to lower your spam score as much as possible.

Subscribe Now

Flesch reading score

Flesch reading score measures how complex a text is. The lower the score, the more difficult the text is to read. The Flesch readability score uses the average length of your sentences (measured by the number of words) and the average number of syllables per word in an equation to calculate the reading ease. Text with a very high Flesch reading ease score (about 100) is straightforward and easy to read, with short sentences and no words of more than two syllables. Usually, a reading ease score of 60-70 is considered acceptable/normal for web copy.

Subscribe Now

Technologies

What powers this email? Every email we receive is parsed to determine the sending ESP and any additional email technologies used.

Subscribe Now

Email Size (not include images)

Font Used

No. Font Name
Subscribe Now

Copyright © 2019–2024 SimilarMail.