Newsletter Subject

A Theory Can Be Bonkers And Not Be Pseudoscience

From

nautil.us

Email Address

newsletters@nautil.us

Sent On

Thu, Sep 28, 2023 11:34 AM

Email Preheader Text

Plus: when a million-acre national park becomes a classroom; the sneaky force behind our sun’s

Plus: when a million-acre national park becomes a classroom; the sneaky force behind our sun’s violent outbursts; this week’s Facts So Romantic; and more. [View in browser](| [Join Nautilus]( Newsletter brought to you by: Did a friend forward this? [Subscribe here.]( This Thursday, your free member newsletter includes one full story, below, by the neuroscientist Anil Seth. After that, be sure to check out this week’s Facts So Romantic. NEUROSCIENCE The Worth of Wild Ideas Even if a leading theory of consciousness is wrong, it can still be useful to science. BY ANIL SETH Earlier this month, the consciousness science community erupted into chaos. [An open letter](, signed by 124 researchers—some specializing in consciousness and others not—made the provocative claim that one of the most widely discussed theories in the field, [Integrated Information Theory]( (IIT), should be considered “pseudoscience.” The uproar that followed sent consciousness social media into a doom spiral of accusation and recrimination, with the fallout covered in [Nature](, [New Scientist](, and elsewhere. Calling something pseudoscience is pretty much the strongest criticism one can make of a theory. It’s a move that should never be taken lightly, especially when more than 100 influential scientists and philosophers do it all at once. The open letter justified the charge primarily on the grounds that IIT has “commitments” to panpsychism—the idea that consciousness is fundamental and ubiquitous—and that the theory “as a whole” may not be empirically testable. [A subsequent piece]( by one of the lead authors of the letter, Hakwan Lau, reframed the charge somewhat: that the claims made for IIT by its proponents and the wider media are not supported by empirical evidence. IIT is a consciousness-first, rather than a brain-first approach. The brainchild of neuroscientist Giulio Tononi, IIT has been around for quite some time. Back in the late 1990s, Tononi published a [paper]( in Science with the Nobel Laureate Gerald Edelman, linking consciousness to mathematical measures of complexity. This paper, which made a lasting impression on me, sowed the seeds of what later became IIT. Tononi published his first [outline of the theory]( itself in 2004 and it has been evolving ever since, with the latest version—[IIT 4.0](—appearing earlier this year. The theory’s counterintuitive and deeply mathematical nature has always attracted controversy and criticism—including [from myself and my colleagues](—but it has certainly become prominent in consciousness science. A survey conducted at the main conference in the field—the annual meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness—found that nearly half of respondents considered it “definitely promising” or “probably promising,” and researchers in the field regularly identify it as one of four main theoretical approaches to consciousness. (The philosopher Tim Bayne did just this in our recent review [paper]( on theories of consciousness for Nature Reviews Neuroscience.) The theory behind IIT is not simple: It turns the standard neuroscientific game—in which consciousness is proposed to emerge from neural activity in the brain—upside down. It takes as its starting point the identification of certain features that must be shared by all conscious experiences, and then asks what properties a physical system (like a brain) must have in order for these features to be present. It is a consciousness-first, rather than a brain-first approach. According to IIT, two features that are essential to any conscious experience are “integration” and “information.” The reasoning is that every conscious experience is unified, “all of a piece,” and that every experience also conveys a large amount of information. Cashing out this claim through the machinery of IIT leads to its central proposal, which is that consciousness is present whenever and wherever a system is more than the sum of its parts—in a highly specific, mathematically precise way. In IIT, the amount of consciousness a system has is tracked by a mathematical quantity called Phi, and, according to the theory, wherever there is non-zero Phi, there will be consciousness, at least to some degree. This implies a restricted form of panpsychism, since instances of non-zero Phi can be found beyond brains, and even in non-biological systems. Some very simple systems can be conscious according to IIT, such as grids of inactive electronic circuitry in a computing device—though the kind of consciousness involved may be very minimal. But many other things—whether simple or complex—will lack consciousness entirely, because they don’t integrate information in the right way. For example, according to IIT, things like tables and chairs wouldn’t be conscious, and neither would artificial intelligence systems in which signals can only flow in one direction. Controversial and counterintuitive it may be, but is IIT pseudoscience? A very general definition of science is the systematic study of natural phenomena through observation, description, theory, and experiment. Scientific theories should be testable, responsive to evidence, and have predictive and explanatory power. A very general definition of pseudoscience is work that claims to be scientific, but falls short in some significant way or ways. Molecular biology and particle physics are examples of science, while homeopathy and astrology are examples of pseudoscience—they are not supported by experimental evidence, and lack any plausible mechanism by which they might operate. The panpsychist implications of IIT are certainly strange. Full-blown panpsychism is a philosophical, metaphysical position, and as such is not open to empirical testing. It is also rather antithetical to science as we know it, which is generally materialist. But although IIT implies a version of panpsychism, it is not equivalent to panpsychism. Arguing against panpsychism, [as I have done](, therefore does not mean arguing against IIT. The fact that a theory can have strange, perhaps untestable consequences, does not mean that it is pseudoscientific. It may be enough for other aspects of the theory to be testable. This happens without controversy in other areas of science. In physics, general relativity implies untestable things, like singularities, while being eminently testable in other ways. It turns the standard neuroscientific game upside down. This leads to the second objection of the letter writers: that IIT “as a whole” may be untestable. This seems to appeal to Karl Popper’s [falsificationist]( philosophy of science, in which a theory could be called pseudoscientific if it cannot be experimentally falsified. But this sets the bar very high, since experimental methods are always improving, and theories can adapt and change over time and still have explanatory and predictive value even if aspects of them remain beyond experimental reach. (Evolutionary theory provides a good example. Core aspects of the theory, such as the mechanisms underlying inheritance, only became testable long after the theory was first developed.) Other philosophies of science could be applied here instead. I’ve always preferred [Imre Lakatos’]( views, in which a research program (which usually extends beyond a theory) is productive if, over time, it generates testable predictions which have explanatory and predictive power. If a research program does not do this, then it is degenerate and will gradually fade away. This view of science is more accommodating to the ebb and flow of ideas, and also to the possibility that some aspects—perhaps even core elements—of a scientific theory may remain unfalsifiable. Quantum mechanics, for example, is highly productive, even though nobody can figure out how to experimentally test its various interpretations (or even what they really mean). From a Lakatosian perspective, IIT squarely qualifies as science. Its core principles are indeed very difficult to test—the same could be said for other leading theories, too—but many testable predictions do follow from IIT. Some of these predictions also follow from other theories, but others [definitely do not](. As these predictions are put to the test in increasingly sophisticated experiments, we will see whether IIT is productive or degenerate. Right now, it is far too early to say. An ongoing series of “[adversarial collaborations](” in consciousness science are particularly interesting for understanding the testability of IIT. These collaborations pit theories against each other using experiments designed so that the theories predict different outcomes. I’ve written about the first of these collaborations elsewhere, and am involved in (though not funded by) a [second](. Although these collaborations are unlikely to land a decisive blow against any of the theories concerned, they are doing excellent, rigorous work, and are undoubtedly driving the field forward. The third objection voiced by IIT opponents—that the evidence base for IIT does not support the claims made by its proponents and the wider media—is worth paying attention to, but it doesn’t justify the charge either. It is certainly very important for researchers to avoid over-claiming and over-promoting, but if they do—and one can argue back-and-forth about whether this is the case for IIT—it doesn’t mean the underlying research is pseudoscience. So long as it satisfies the criteria for science, it is science, whether appropriately communicated or not. I believe IIT meets the criteria necessary for science: It sets out to explain a natural phenomenon using a rigorous theoretical approach, one that generates testable predictions that have the potential for explanatory and predictive power. Reasserting the scientific status of IIT matters for reasons that extend beyond its specific pros and cons as a theory. It matters firstly because of the outward impression. The motivation behind the open letter was to ensure the long-term health of consciousness science through a surgical strike against the perceived oversized influence of IIT. But it could have the opposite effect. Outsiders may lose trust in a field that can’t seem to sort out science from pseudoscience among its own leading theories. Such perceptions could be disastrous, given how hard consciousness researchers have worked to establish the field’s well-deserved legitimacy. Levels of funding, the ability to attract smart young researchers into the field, and the potential for consciousness research to make a positive impact in the world could all be threatened. But there is something even more fundamental at stake here, which is the right to be wrong. The statistician George Box is often quoted with saying that “all models are wrong, but some are useful.” In fact what he said, in a [1987 book](, was “Remember that all models are wrong; the practical question is how wrong do they have to be to not be useful.” The theory is indeed a bit bonkers, but it could be on the right track. IIT is very likely wrong. It may well be more wrong than other leading theories of consciousness, which are also likely to be wrong. It may be even more wrong than [my own theory]( (which is very different from IIT). But even if it is very wrong, it can still be very useful. IIT can be usefully wrong firstly because it can inspire related ideas. I’ve worked on some of these with my colleagues under the banner of “[weak IIT,](” which gives up some theoretical ambition for gains in empirical applicability. The influential work by Marcello Massimini and his group on [measuring the level of consciousness in brain-injured patients]( was also inspired by early versions of IIT (although these results are compatible with other theories as well). And there is plenty more valuable research out there, as well as up and coming work, that has been inspired to some degree by the theory—[the same is true for the other leading theories,]( too. The second reason may be even more important, and is the one I really want to underline here. It is precisely the challenging, counterintuitive nature of IIT that ought to be valued, even if the theory itself turns out to be empirically wrong. Although consciousness science has made huge strides, a deep sense of mystery persists about the nature of consciousness and its relation to brains, bodies, and the physical world in general. Even if we overestimate the difficulties involved, [which I think we do](, it seems unlikely that we’ll arrive at a satisfactory scientific account of consciousness without some radically creative thinking. If we banish IIT to the wastelands of pseudoscience, dismissing it in part because of its strangeness, we risk stifling exactly the kind of creative thinking that we may need. The theory is indeed a bit bonkers, but it is a brave attempt to say something genuinely new. And who knows, it could even be on the right track. So let’s not merely reject the charge of pseudoscience. Instead let’s celebrate what is weird and unusual about it, while making sure to not over-hype or over-claim. As long as theories remain within the bounds of the scientific method, they have every right to be wrong. Lead image: Master1305 / Shutterstock More from Nautilus: • [When a million-acre national park becomes a classroom]( • [The sneaky force behind our sun’s violent outbursts]( Experience the endless possibilities and deep human connections that science offers [JOIN TODAY]( FACTS SO ROMANTIC The Best Things We Learned Today Although the Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness implies a version of panpsychism, it is not equivalent to panpsychism. Nautilus Gorongosa has the only master’s program in the world run entirely within a national park. Nautilus The snapping of a magnetic field from the sun releases an enormous amount of pent-up energy in the form of solar flares. Nautilus The people most likely to be engaging with popular science are ironically the least aware of how limited their knowledge is. Nautilus The tiny box jellyfish is barely the size of a fingernail yet can learn without a brain. Nautilus Artificial cells can be equipped with magnetic particles (a rarity in nature) that allows them to move in response to a magnetic field. Nautilus P.S. The American astronomer Edwin Hubble, after whom the Hubble Space Telescope is named, died on this day in 1953. In 1939, he paid a visit to an ailing friend. Depressed and interred at Las Encinas Hospital, a mental health facility, the friend, an actor and playwright named John Emerson, [asked Hubble what—spiritually, cosmically—he believed in.]( “The whole thing is so much bigger than I am,” he told Emerson, “and I can’t understand it, so I just trust myself to it, and forget about it.” Today’s newsletter was written by Brian Gallagher Thanks for reading. [Tell us](mailto:brian.gallagher@nautil.us?subject=&body=) your thoughts on today’s note. Plus, [browse our archive]( of past print issues, and inspire a friend to sign up for [the Nautilus newsletter.]( [Facebook]( [Twitter]( [Instagram]( Copyright © 2023 NautilusNext, All rights reserved.You were subscribed to the newsletter from [nautil.us](. Our mailing address is: NautilusNext360 W 36th Street, 7S,New York, NY 10018 Don't want to hear from us anymore? [Unsubscribe](

EDM Keywords (264)

year wrong written worth worked work whether wherever well weird week ways wastelands want visit view version useful uproar unusual untestable unlikely unified understanding understand underline ubiquitous turns trust true tracked today time thursday threatened thoughts though think theory theories testable testability test takes system sure supported support sun sum subscribed subscribe strangeness still stake specializing sowed sort snapping size simple signals sign shared sets seems seem seeds scientific science saying say satisfies said romantic right results response researchers remember relation recrimination reasons reasoning rarity quite put pseudoscientific pseudoscience proposed proponents properties promoting program productive present predictive predictions precisely potential possibility plenty piece philosophies philosophers people pent parts part paper panpsychism paid overestimate ought others order open one newsletter never nautilus nature must move month models minimal measuring mean may master many make made machinery long limited likely level let least leads land lack knows knowledge know kind justify ironically involved interred integration instead inspired inspire information indeed important implies iit identification ideas idea hype homeopathy hear group grounds grids gives gains funding funded fundamental friend forth form forget follow flow first figure field features far facts fact explanatory explain examples example evidence even establish essential equivalent equipped ensure enough engaging energy emerge ebb early difficult different degree degenerate day criteria counterintuitive could consciousness conscious cons complexity complex compatible commitments colleagues collaborations classroom claims claiming claim check charge chaos change chairs certainly celebrate case cannot brainchild bounds bonkers believed barely bar banner avoid astrology association aspects asks arrive around areas archive applied appeal amount also allows adapt actor accusation according accommodating ability 2004 1953 1939

Marketing emails from nautil.us

View More
Sent On

30/05/2024

Sent On

29/05/2024

Sent On

28/05/2024

Sent On

26/05/2024

Sent On

23/05/2024

Sent On

22/05/2024

Email Content Statistics

Subscribe Now

Subject Line Length

Data shows that subject lines with 6 to 10 words generated 21 percent higher open rate.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Number of Words

The more words in the content, the more time the user will need to spend reading. Get straight to the point with catchy short phrases and interesting photos and graphics.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Number of Images

More images or large images might cause the email to load slower. Aim for a balance of words and images.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Time to Read

Longer reading time requires more attention and patience from users. Aim for short phrases and catchy keywords.

Subscribe Now

Average in this category

Subscribe Now

Predicted open rate

Subscribe Now

Spam Score

Spam score is determined by a large number of checks performed on the content of the email. For the best delivery results, it is advised to lower your spam score as much as possible.

Subscribe Now

Flesch reading score

Flesch reading score measures how complex a text is. The lower the score, the more difficult the text is to read. The Flesch readability score uses the average length of your sentences (measured by the number of words) and the average number of syllables per word in an equation to calculate the reading ease. Text with a very high Flesch reading ease score (about 100) is straightforward and easy to read, with short sentences and no words of more than two syllables. Usually, a reading ease score of 60-70 is considered acceptable/normal for web copy.

Subscribe Now

Technologies

What powers this email? Every email we receive is parsed to determine the sending ESP and any additional email technologies used.

Subscribe Now

Email Size (not include images)

Font Used

No. Font Name
Subscribe Now

Copyright © 2019–2024 SimilarMail.